Does every nonempty scheme contains a closed point?
Answer: No. There exist nonempty schemes with no closed points.
However, for quasi-compact schemes the statement is true.
Recall the following
Easy Lemma: A scheme X is quasi-compact iff it can be written as a finite union of affine schemes.
--------
Answer: No. There exist nonempty schemes with no closed points.
However, for quasi-compact schemes the statement is true.
Recall the following
Easy Lemma: A scheme X is quasi-compact iff it can be written as a finite union of affine schemes.
--------
Quasi-Compact Schemes have Closed Points
Let X be a quasi-compact scheme
Proof 1: (Stack Exchange) As X is quasi-compact, it is a finite union of affine pieces X = \bigcup_{i=1}^n U_i. Notice that a subset of X is closed iff it is closed in every U_i.
Suppose X does not contain any closed point.
Let x_1 be a closed point of U_1, then \overline{\{ x_1\}} \cap U_1 = \{x_1\}, i.e. x_1 is the unique point in U_1 of its closure.
As x is not closed, x must not be closed in some U_i. WLOG, assume x_1 is not closed in U_2. Then \overline{\{ x_1\}} \cap U_2, being a closed subset of an affine scheme, must contain some closed point x_2 of U_2 other than x_1.
Repeating the argument, we can find x_3 \in \overline{\{ x_2\}} \subset \overline{\{ x_1\}} such that x_3 is closed in U_3 but x_3 \not \in U_2 \cup U_1. Continuing the process we will get x_{n+1} \not \in U_{n} \cup U_{n-1}\cup \cdots \cup U_1, a contradiction.
Remark. We constructed a sequence x_1, \ldots, x_n, \ldots satisfying:
Proof 2: (Akhil) Using Quasi-compactness + Zorn's Lemma, we can show that X has a minimal nonempty closed set Z. We can put a scheme structure on Z such that the underlying topology is the subspace topology. As Z is a scheme, it contains an affine piece U. As Z - U is a closed subset of Z, by minimality of Z we must have Z- U = \emptyset, i.e. Z = U is affine so it must contains a closed point.
Proof 3: (Mine)
If X has no closed points, then the closure of every point contains a point other than itself.
Thus we have a nested sequence
\overline{\{x_1\}} \supsetneq \overline{\{x_2\}} \supsetneq \overline{\{x_3\}} \supsetneq \overline{\{x_4\}} \overline \cdots.
On each affine piece, the sequence terminates as affine schemes are Noetherian. As X as finitely many affine pieces, the sequence terminates in X also. Thus there is some x such that \overline{\{x\}} does not contain any closed point other than x, contradiction.
Suppose X does not contain any closed point.
Let x_1 be a closed point of U_1, then \overline{\{ x_1\}} \cap U_1 = \{x_1\}, i.e. x_1 is the unique point in U_1 of its closure.
As x is not closed, x must not be closed in some U_i. WLOG, assume x_1 is not closed in U_2. Then \overline{\{ x_1\}} \cap U_2, being a closed subset of an affine scheme, must contain some closed point x_2 of U_2 other than x_1.
Repeating the argument, we can find x_3 \in \overline{\{ x_2\}} \subset \overline{\{ x_1\}} such that x_3 is closed in U_3 but x_3 \not \in U_2 \cup U_1. Continuing the process we will get x_{n+1} \not \in U_{n} \cup U_{n-1}\cup \cdots \cup U_1, a contradiction.
Remark. We constructed a sequence x_1, \ldots, x_n, \ldots satisfying:
- x_i is a closed point of U_i;
- x_j is a specialization of x_i for every j > i;
- x_i's are all distinct
- x_j \not \in U_i for all j < i.
Proof 2: (Akhil) Using Quasi-compactness + Zorn's Lemma, we can show that X has a minimal nonempty closed set Z. We can put a scheme structure on Z such that the underlying topology is the subspace topology. As Z is a scheme, it contains an affine piece U. As Z - U is a closed subset of Z, by minimality of Z we must have Z- U = \emptyset, i.e. Z = U is affine so it must contains a closed point.
Proof 3: (Mine)
If X has no closed points, then the closure of every point contains a point other than itself.
Thus we have a nested sequence
\overline{\{x_1\}} \supsetneq \overline{\{x_2\}} \supsetneq \overline{\{x_3\}} \supsetneq \overline{\{x_4\}} \overline \cdots.
On each affine piece, the sequence terminates as affine schemes are Noetherian. As X as finitely many affine pieces, the sequence terminates in X also. Thus there is some x such that \overline{\{x\}} does not contain any closed point other than x, contradiction.
This kind of argument is useful in proving some property (that might not be open) holds for every point of X if it holds for closed point of X. For example, we use this argument to check that for a quasi-compact scheme X, it suffices to check reducedness at closed points.
Main Usage
We say that property P of points of a scheme is open if whenever a point x satisfies P, a neighborhood of it must satisfy P also.
Let X be a quasi-compact scheme. To show that all points of X satisfies P. It suffices to show that all \emph{closed} points of X do.
Explanation: As every closed subset of a quasi-compact scheme is quasi-compact, it must contains a closed point. In particular, for every x \in X, \overline{\{x\}} contains a closed point y. By definition of closure, we have that every neighborhood of y must contain x. So any covering of closed points must also be a cover of X.
I don't think your proof works in full generality, since an affine scheme is Noetherian iff the ring whose spectrum it is isomorphic to is Noetherian. Of course, in most situations the rings we are working over are Noetherian, and my first instinct was to do something like you did in your proof, but I don't think it works, unfortunately.
ReplyDelete